"... their training and professional culture can arguably predispose them to do so," writes Elizabeth Mertz -- about scholars who merge law and social science.
My first reaction to that was: arguably? You're already backing off on the accusation with "predispose." Personally, I would be skeptical of anything written by a law professor.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
15 comments:
There's no peer review of much of what lawprofs write (which is not necessarily the end-all-be-all of quality) academically and their op-eds are edited by newspaper editors -- and what the hell do they know? The Volokh guys periodically hash out the "law review articles are too long, etc." jazz
Blogprofs are commentator-reviewed however -- very powerful (and quick!) stuff.
Althouse
"Formidable law blogger Ann Althouse." – Slate
"The divine Ms. Althouse." – Terry Teachout
"Personally, I would be skeptical of anything written by a law professor." - Ann Althouse
I agree with this premise but disagree with the larger point Mertz seems to be making. The purpose of the adversarial structure of the legal system is to arrive at truth by having competing views zealously advocated. Whatever its flaws, I think this structure is a more effective means of accomplishing that goal than any alternative.
In the academic world--a marketplace of ideas--treating one's intellectual product as a client is not necessarily a bad thing, so long as basic standards of intellectual honesty and open debate are observed. In an academic environment in which intellectual diversity is valued, vigorous debate will result in ideas rising and falling on merit. I don't think it is necessary for advocates of those ideas to try (or pretend) to act as scientists.
The larger problem than law professors treating their ideas as clients is the fiction that the published work of social scientists is purely scientific work. While empirical study in the social sciences is deserving of respect as true science, most of the final work product created by academics in the social sciences is laden with subjective social and political judgments. Better to treat such work as what it is, and let it rise or fall on the merits, than to shield it from criticism from outside the social science academy by attacking such criticism as unscientific.
To put it a little more concretely, if a law professor publishes something critical of the work of a social scientist, I would want to see whose view is more persuasively stated, without starting from the assumption that the law professor's work is more prone to bias and thus must be looked upon with greater skepticism.
I hope this doesn't sound like an attack on the social sciences. Obviously, such work is important. I just cannot accept the idea that there is some higher level of scientific rigor distinguishing most of what is published in the social sciences from what is published by legal academics.
David, I don't know your work or education background (so I apologize if I'm telling you something you know well already), but if you think "metapragmatism" is bad you should read some modern (say last 40 years especially) literary criticism. Ugh! It is awful and pretentious -- "shitty" a common man migt say. Full of 50-Cent (no not "Fitty" Cent) words and sentences that make Joseph Conrad seems "punchy". No wonder students hate studying literature. These creatures suck the joy out of it.
Is Lurkette up to seven names, or eight? I've lost count (if not interest).
It sounds like the goal of this field of study is to deconstruct the legal opinions of various judges. In the humanities, this technique has revealed that Western culture, white males, and Christianity are all quite bad. Something tells me these lawyers won't be "scientifically" analyzing the liberal opinions.
I agree with jeff d; the adversarial system relies on free inquiry between equals, not the opinion of self-appointed brahmins, to maintain societal order.
Is that blog a parody about law professors?
A sensitive question must be asked: are these folks really competent to teach law students the skills they will actually need as lawyers? I mean, do they understand law as logical argumentation about rules applied to facts or do they see it as uncovering "metalinguistic" and "metapragmatic cues", whatever they are?
It may be better for all concerned if these New Legal Realists work on their theories in anthropology and sociology departments rather than law schools.
A sensitive question must be asked: are these folks really competent to teach law students the skills they will actually need as lawyers? I mean, do they understand law as logical argumentation about rules applied to facts or do they see it as uncovering "metalinguistic" and "metapragmatic cues", whatever they are?
There's a broader question to be asked about what a legal education ought to entail. It's certainly not primarily a matter of teaching substantive black-letter law. Nor is it really focussed on what lawyers actually do all day (not trial advocacy or brief-writing, which are the two "practical" lawyer skills law schools tend to focus on). So perhaps they're ideally selected for a particular vision of law school, one not mostly about teaching skills students will need as lawyers.
That out of the way, a lot of adjunct professors at the law school I attended were practicing lawyers down in the city (NY). So they certainly had the skills necessary for work as real lawyers. They weren't exactly confined to the ivory tower. I expect that the interaction between adjunct and full-time faculty would further prevent the full-time faculty from becoming totally insulated in their field too.
Jacques, Magoo: You haven't fully meditated on the koan.
"Personally, I would be skeptical of anything written by a law professor."
Yeah, sure you would.
Personally, I would be skeptical of anything written by a law professor.
Roshi, my answer is mu.
Perhaps because I am a scientist and engineer and strive for intellectual honesty, and I cannot perceive that there is a koan to answer. We strive to be properly skeptical of all things and to test and so your statement resolves to a tautology. As Feynman instructs us:
The first principle is that you must not fool yourself--and you are the easiest person to fool. So you have to be very careful about that. After you've not fooled yourself, it's easy not to fool other scientists. You just have to be honest in a conventional way after that.
I would like to add something that's not essential to the science, but something I kind of believe, which is that you should not fool the layman when you're talking as a scientist. I am not trying to tell you what to do about cheating on your wife, or fooling your girlfriend, or something like that, when you're not trying to be a scientist, but just trying to be an ordinary human being. We'll leave those problems up to you and your rabbi. I'm talking about a specific, extra type of integrity that is not lying, but bending over backwards to show how you're maybe wrong, that you ought to have when acting as a scientist. And this is our responsibility as scientists, certainly to other scientists, and I think to laymen.
For example, I was a little surprised when I was talking to a friend who was going to go on the radio. He does work on cosmology and astronomy, and he wondered how he would explain what the applications of his work were. "Well," I said, "there aren't any." He said, "Yes, but then we won't get support for more research of this kind." I think that's kind of dishonest. If you're representing yourself as a scientist, then you should explain to the layman what you're doing-- and if they don't support you under those circumstances, then that's their decision.
One example of the principle is this: If you've made up your mind to test a theory, or you want to explain some idea, you should always decide to publish it whichever way it comes out. If we only publish results of a certain kind, we can make the argument look good. We must publish BOTH kinds of results.
I say that's also important in giving certain types of government advice. Supposing a senator asked you for advice about whether drilling a hole should be done in his state; and you decide it would be better in some other state. If you don't publish such a result, it seems to me you're not giving scientific advice. You're being used. If your answer happens to come out in the direction the government or the politicians like, they can use it as an argument in their favor; if it comes out the other way, they don't publish at all. That's not giving scientific advice.
Roshi, how about examining this puzzle:
What do you get when you are afraid to lose face and you okay torture?
First of all, thanks to Ann for linking up to our guest blog at ELS. And, I can't say I blame anyone who found my terminology obnoxious -- I didn't even try to explain it! I definitely should've resisted the urge to add my "personal footnote" about linguistics. Sorry. It's actually much more sensible than it sounds, but hard to explain in a sound bite. And I didn't want to highjack the whole NLR blog with an essay on anthropological linguistics.
In less technical language, my postscript basically points out that we can misunderstand each other if we don't ask whether we share assumptions about what we're doing when we're talking. The very same words ("get out!") can mean something quite different if you think we're having a fight, and I'm thinking we're kidding around.
I think both law profs and social scientists are guilty of assuming too much when they try to talk with each other.
Now, we could just all give up. But I think that would be silly. We have a lot to teach each other.
And, whatever you think of "metalanguage" -- please don't visit your ire on the core new legal realist mission! That was just me talking --
Going to take a slap at Stewart Macaulay, too, Ann? Or do you save that charming behavior only for female colleagues?
AJD: What slap? Do you read with understanding?
Post a Comment